"The idea that I have never ceased to develop is that in the end a man can always make something out of what is made of him."
--J.P. Sartre
Friday, September 30, 2011
Calculative Thinking & The Averaging of the Da-sein
Heidegger's philosophy retains a complexity that has already been noted in class several times. However, what has not been touched on is the consistency of ideas that, in fact, link the entire Heidegger reading together – despite the constant presence of confusion and appearance of contradiction at first glance.
Heidegger’s philosophy is characterized by interweaving of his concepts and the terminology he uses to define them. At the core of Heidegger’s philosophy is the idea of “Da-sein” – the being with its own Being as an issue. This being inherently exist in the world, and cannot be separated from others because its condition of “being-there-too” with others. Da-sein cannot be thought of as ever isolated from others because the two are intrinsically linked. However, it can be distinguished from them (Sec 26).
Though, Da-sein is absorbed into the world, there is no “universal subject” that is composed of multiple Da-sein. There is, however, the presence of the “they” – or “Das Mam” – which has the potential to cause Da-sein to lose itself. It is possible at any point in which a Da-sein is “being-with-one-another” – such as in public transportation. The Da-sein becomes a part of the “the being of the others” and it can become so that the others become less distinct, and then Da-sein loses its ability to be its own being; it becomes ruled by the they. This process is known as “levelling down”, in which the Da-sein loses what makes it distinguishable – it does everything the same way “they” do(Sec 27).
It is this blind conformity that Heidegger rallies against. He referred to this as “publicness” and it was something he found to be unwanted. “Publicness” was to limit the possibilities of being and to work within in the same structure as “they” do (Sec 27). While apart of the public, the Da-sein “flees from though.” It does not have its Being as a concern, and its thoughts become purely calculative – focus of facts, computations, and practicality – rather than the typical meditative quality – reflective of experience – they are intended to have.
The concept of thoughtlessness versus reflection is a consistent theme of Heidegger. He especially stresses it in his “Discourse on Thinking,” and the Da-sein is defined by meditative thinking. Therefore, not only are the ideas and complex thoughts all linked, but remain within the very same realm. There is a brilliance in the use of repetitious terminology to link all the concepts.
As confusing as Heidegger’s syntax can be, I found an appreciation for this coherence of thought which many great thinkers do not maintain over several works, and it did raise a point of interest about not just the material but existence. Perhaps, all that which composes a being, such as the Da-sein, is not a disconnected collage of random character traits but a network of influences and characteristics that may be distinguished but cannot be removed from one another. Or it may just be we are just jumbled sums of experience up to this point.
Slaves of the they
I have found these particular passages from Heidegger (and the subsequent explanation of these passages in class) have proposed some interesting ideas about our existence. Particularly, Heidegger’s ideas about the modes in which das sein can be the they. The idea of distantiality is essentially the fact that we compare and measure ourselves with others. As we do not want to appear too extreme or different we suppress this distantiality and the more we suppress it the more average we become. This idea of averaging, which causes the leveling down of society, makes us become more and more like each other. The leveling down of society is an especially frightening idea. To think that the bar is lower than it potentially could be is points to how much control the they has over us.
Social media, Wikipedia, google news, the list goes on. We are all, to steal a term from Nietzsche, slaves to the they. If I am making a false statement by saying that someone please correct me, but if I understand it correctly this is the way it sounds. The they is relieving just about everyone of responsibility and individuality. Without responsibility or individuality can Das Sein exhist. I, for one, do not believe it can. If we rely too heavily on the they we risk losing the Das Sein which is the one thing that differentiates us from every other animal on the planet.
Can we, as individuals, really exist as individuals if we all so frequently participate in the they? In my opinion, modern Western society has turned us into sheepish slaves of the they.
Dasein vs Das Man
The Essence of Da-Sein and its Implications
As far as we know, only human beings fall under the category of Da-Sein, that is, the being which has its own Being as an issue. Although we have this criterion, it does not explicate what is essential to Da-Sein. In Heidegger's words, "The 'essence' of this being [Da-Sein] lies in its to be" (119), which of course is a difficult phrase to comprehend. I think Patrick got us on the right track when he said that this relates to the "existence precedes essence" mantra of the existentialists. We contrasted the essence of Da-Sein with the essence of any other ordinary object, e.g., a table. (For the sake of simplicity, we will leave animals out of consideration for now.) The table cannot be said to have its essence within its being. Rather, a table is so because it is constructed by people who have the form, or the essence, of the table in mind, meaning that the essence is prior to the table's existence. To put it another way, and the way that Dr. Johnson once characterized it, the table's being does not depend on its constant actualization of being a table. It simply is so because it is. The same, however, cannot be said for human beings. We do constantly actualize our being. Whatever, or more appropriately whoever, we are does depend on our making it so. But since our making it so presupposes that we are there to make it, it must be said that our existence is prior to our essence. (Sartre explains this idea in a similar manner in Existentialism is a Humanism.)
Let's take a second to evaluate the claim that's being made here and see what kind of conditions are necessary for this claim to be true. Earlier philosophers like Aquinas and Aristotle probably did not see humans as having essences fulfilled through one's existence. Rather, humans fell under the category of "rational animal" which inhered somehow in the cosmos. This usually implies a sort of theological or teleological worldview, where humans fulfill their pre-existing essences through their own existence. This does not seem to be the case for the existentialists. Heidegger's thought seems to extend from Nietzsche's nihilist stance that the world is really just a chaotic place and that the perceived orderly universe is just an illusion. Indeed, such world conditions seem necessary if we are to make the claim that Da-Sein has its essence in its being. Should we then abandon all teleological viewpoints?
(Footnotes:
I credit Patrick Shade for being a partial source for some ideas expressed in the third paragraph.
If I am misrepresenting existentialist thought or am getting too ahead of myself, please comment and let me know. I've read existentialist literature and writing about existentialism before, but I do admit I have a confused picture of it.)
Heidegger and Sociology
For Heidegger, being in the mode of the they-self is an inauthentic mode of being for Dasein, yet it is a part of Dasein’s average everydayness to be in this mode. Heidegger realizes that we regularly appeal to the ‘they’ as a way of dealing with our everyday lives. This is not something we can get away from. It is part of Dasein’s ontological structure insofar as it is a Being-with-others. While we may be predisposed towards deburdening ourselves by projecting the ‘they’ it is still not an authentic mode of being for Dasein. Dasein is not Dasein when it is in the mode of the they-self because it loses its ‘mineness’. It no longer is for its own Being, but for the Being of the ‘they’.
This projecting of the ‘they’ is very similar to how sociology conceives of the way in which the individual is socially constructed by the group. The sociologist is generally interested in what different societies take to be knowledge as opposed to what knowledge is itself. The basic response is that society is a kind of normalizing force the instructs the individuals about how to act. The simple act of congregating in a group is enough to create a collective ‘moral’ feeling about how one should act.
This kind of naïve social epistemology has always bothered me. Heidegger’s account seems to me to be an accurate and powerful challenge to the idea that the socializing, normalizing force of the ‘they’ is the place one turns to for knowledge, or justification of that knowledge. Has anyone else come up against this problem? I know that this post goes a little outside the scope of this class, but I was wondering if anyone else has taken any sociology classes. In a way, the sociologist is committing the same offence as the lazy relativist, but the sociologist is much more rigorous in her approach. Let me know what you think.
Heidegger's Human
For example, his very distinction of the difference between data and understanding, between the calculative and meditative varieties of thought, seems to me to be a rephrasing of the arguments of thinkers like Descartes or Kant as to what is unique about human intelligence: namely that we do not merely experience impressions of the world but are able to relate them to one another within conceptual frameworks that provide meaning.
Similarly (as I think I mentioned in class), the defintion of Da-sein as defined by the ability of a being to have its own being (or is it Being?) as a question presupposes the existence of a kind of intelligence capable of asking any question at all, which seems to me to be even more fundamental (chairs don't ask themselves about either being or Being, as far as we know). In summary, I was left feeling as if all of Heidgger's thought was less subversive or revolutionary than one would think. Then again, he was a Nazi.
Am I offbase on all this?
Friday, September 23, 2011
Ascetcism...
By definition Asceticism is a life style of abstinence from multiple worldly pleasure with the purpose of pursing religious or spiritual goal. In the christian and Indian Religion it serves as a teaching of salvation and liberation-a transformation for the mind and soul A way to create a freedom in an individual's life.
Nietzche divides the meaning up of what asceticism is in 6 different parts, individualizing it for 6 different types of people: the artist, philosopher, women, philosophical causalities, priests and saints. He goes into detail as to how each individual type experiences and how the ascetic ideal affects them. After reading sources on this I tried to come up with a meaning of what Nietzche was saying and I came up with this definition. It is the yes-saying of our willingness to test our limits, our willingness to struggle to achieve full power over ourselves and possibly nature.
But what makes this ideal life affirming and is this what he means by the birds of prey not being able to assert themselves.
http://www.themystica.com/mystica/articles/a/asceticism.html
Lack of Necessity as an Indication of Will
As we studied in greater depth the meaning and intent of Nietzsche’s allegory in paragraph 13 this week, I became concerned with the idea of determinism that such an argument implies, that is, the concept that the subject cannot be separated from the action, which essentially eliminates the existence of choice; if each person is imbued with particular qualities, the nature of which cannot be expressed as anything other than the essentials of that quality then, according to Nietzsche, we are necessarily unable to choose our actions, a belief in which illustrates our distortion of this fact and acceptance of the slave morality.
His chosen allegory certainly accepts this fact and implies a natural hierarchy that is independent of societal or moral constructions; it simply is what it is. However, it is this focus on the natural aspect of the relationship that I find limiting to his argument and, therefore, allows for the inclusion of will or choice. His metaphor has a naturalistic quality because of its reliance upon animal relationships; nature implies impulse, which is driven by necessity. For example, the reason that the birds attack and feed on the lambs is not simply because they are strong and must find an outlet for their strength, but that they must have something to eat, as is required by their nature. In this sense, the “what is” is dominated and governed by necessity. This remains consistent with Nietzsche’s point: the birds cannot help but to exercise their strength; it is their natures, but only insofar as nature makes it necessary to live.
This concept of necessity may have parallels in human society. For instance in economic situations: the existence of an elite, rich upper-class necessarily requires the existence of a poor lower-class. However, human existence is no longer completely governed by naturalistic boundaries, as defined by mere necessity. Modern society has created the idea of luxury beyond the necessities simply required to live. Therefore, there exist moments where we are not acting according to the laws of necessity. If that particular action is not required for us to live, how is it that we can conceive of acting on it? Where necessity does not drive, the absence of any guidance implies a choice is required. We can act one way or the other because neither action is necessary. This seems to allow for at least the need, if not existence of human will. And the existence of choice implies that a right or wrong decision has the potential of being made, which implies the existence of an inherent morality. If the strong man walks outside and punches the weaker man in the face, the absence of necessity would lead us to believe that such an action was inherently wrong; we would not accept the claim that the strong man was simply exercising his strength because he could not do otherwise…
During our discussion on Thursday, I found it interesting that we could not come up with a proper term for the failure to follow through with a promise. Such an instance is not necessarily a lie, but rather an overestimation of one's command of the future.Typically when a promise is made, the promiser has every intention of following through with it. If the promiser never had any such intention, it would in fact be a lie and could not be termed a promise at all. As was stated, the future is so uncertain that it almost seems foolish to promise something when you are unable to ensure, with absolute certainty, that the action will be completed.
Suppose we make a distinction between an promise unfulfilled and a promise broken, the former being a failure due extenuating circumstances and the latter being a failure due to an individual's choice. From an objective standpoint, it seems unfair to punish someone for a promise unfulfilled because the failure was outside of his or her control (although one could also argue that the individual should avoid making promises that cannot be kept). The notion of being forgiven for unfulfilled promises becomes even trickier when applied to the present day creditor-debtor relationship. People buy houses, cars, and even furniture, all the while thinking that they will be able to keep up with the monthly payments. Initially they are successful, but eventually taxing circumstances (no pun intended) get the best of them and finances get tied up in other things. Loans fail to be paid off, and then legal actions must be taken. Typically people do not choose to skip bill payments for the thrill of it; if a payment is skipped, it's because the funds are lacking. Thus the promise of their payment is unfulfilled rather than broken, but because they are bound by contract, it cannot be brushed aside or forgiven. It seems a great deal of financial woes would be resolved if people made a habit of making purchases with currency rather than with promises.
Slavish Morality is Natural
On Thursday we discussed how this moral system applies to human nature. In the second essay of The Genealogy of Morals, the origin of guilt is said to originate from the “most primitive relationship among persons there is, in the relationship between buyer and seller, creditor and debtor” (88). We said in class that this type of creditor-debtor relationship makes sense because human beings have a tendency to measure, value, and evaluate.
The concept that we use the slavish moral system in all, or almost all, situations makes sense. I do not understand, or more so agree, with Nietzsche’s view that the elite, noble class should rule with their value system of “good and bad.” If the noble class was to rule with their value system, would our concept of guilt even exist? As of the system of “good and evil” in place now, we compare ourselves and others using the system as an evaluation tool. If we did not have such a system in place at all, would humans have evaluated things? Would humans have different characteristics?
I think that if the slavish morality system was not in place, then there might not be a sense of guilt, since we would not be comparing ourselves to a system. Rather, everything would just be assigned as “good” or “bad” and there would not be anything more to it. Hence, Jesus would not have been seen as a redeemer because lack of guilt would make it so that there is nothing to him to redeem from all of humanity.
In other words, I think that the slavish morality system is natural and necessary for life. It coincides with the natural characteristics that humans have (i.e. the tendency for human beings to measure, value, and evaluate).
What do you think? Do you think that the slavish morality is necessary? Do you think Nietzsche is right in saying that the elite class should dominate with their value system? Would guilt exist if this was the case (elite dominating)?
The Strongest of The Weak
And the winner is....
Jesus?
How can Jesus be the strongest of the weak?
Nietzche explains the origins of our modern value system by first explaining what it was before. He says that what predated our current system was a system that gave value to the strong and the noble. It makes sense. The people that were originally on top of the natural hierarchy were the ones that assumed the roles of "value-makers". The things that were noble and strong were considered "good", and obviously, the things that were not strong became "weak". But somewhere down the line (centuries later I assume), a priestly caste used God and eventually Jesus as a catalyst or a means for this reciprocated value system. Unlike the aristocratic morality system, this system treated the strong (master) as evil and the weak (the slaves) as good. Nietzche explains that this is natural for the weak to not want to accept this faith.
So what happens? The priestly caste devises a plan to separate the good and bad by making it a choice to be weak or strong. This illusion makes it a choice to be strong or weak by completely ignoring the natural hierarchy (the natural deterministic characteristics). By saying this, you can essentially place blame on the strong for being strong and the weak for being weak. Thus, creating good and evil. Essentially, it is a struggle between determinism and free will (reminds me of Dostoevsky).
So how does this relate to Jesus? Well according to Nietzche, Jesus would be considered the strongest of the weak. He is the one who rallied the weak to change the moral system. Well, I question that that means that He is weak. I believe that there is a separation from the church and Jesus. The priestly caste is life-denying. They assume that Jesus would call the strong and noble evil, while in fact I do not see that to be the case. First, Jesus is considered a God - a figure that is beyond all things. He is life-affirming. Unlike the priestly caste who condemn the strong, Jesus does not even pays them attention. To me those are the attributes of a strong person.
It is my understanding that Jesus preached about choices and decisions and that he gave us free will to choose between the good and bad. But did he live his life that way. I argue that he does not. He lives his life beyond that. He does not react to the strong. He does not react to his oppression. No, he accepts it whole-heartedly. That makes him strong. Yes, he preached about free-will and choices, but that is not how he lived his life. He is life affirming and a strong individual.
Tell me what you think.
Wednesday, September 21, 2011
The natural world
Friday, September 16, 2011
Nietzsche and Free Will
This idea of being held accountable made me think of our discussion on Tuesday about freewill and determinism. From what we saw in Notes from Underground, the human being is essentially free. She resists every formula suggested to dictate her behavior. She will act irrationality simply to avoid becoming predictable. Does Nietzsche agree with this conception of the human as being free? If we look at the example above, it appears that he would say that human beings are very much determined. Those who act strong are the strong. They can’t help themselves or do anything about it. It is only after the slave revolt that they are given a ‘choice’ by the slaves. Nietzsche seems to be insinuating that this is actually a false choice. We have no real free will to choose.
It is strange, then, that Nietzsche is so interested in the ‘will to power’ or even a ‘will’ to anything. If Nietzsche is in fact a determinist, what could willing something actually do? One could possibly will some life-affirming principle, but one cannot will a change in one’s nature (i.e. insofar as one is strong or weak, etc.). The ‘willing’ involved in the life-affirmation process is not the robust sense of will that we usually think of. However, what we might consider a ‘robust’ account of will may just be slave morality’s corruption of the understanding of will. Perhaps a genealogy of the concept of will (along the same lines and the genealogy of the concepts of ‘good and bad’ and ‘good and evil’) might be in order.
I’d like to leave y’all with this question: Does Nietzsche provide a freewill or determinist account of the human being? Or are such categories simply a function of the slave morality and as such not appropriate to use?
Does Free Will Exist?
Consider the Middle Ground
There are quite a few points that Nietzsche argues with which I must admit leave me utterly bewildered. Neither the slave nor master classifications are intrinsically superior – despite their syntax – (though it has already been argued that he has a bias to the “strong,” “noble” class) but is it not the weak class that provided for the creation and reassessment of values? Yes, there was rationalism and thinking that alludes to the enlightened philosophers within the content of the essay – which from this context Nietzsche disapproves; however, is it not the slave revolt – the reaction to the “good” – that opens up the dialogue to existential examinations?
Though the slave revolt is described as a simple inverse of the previous principles, it still changed those values – technically to the other extreme. Does that not also mean that it allows for a grey area for which philosophical thought and questions can maneuver freely?
It seems that Nietzsche is criticizing the whole affair as pointless because the good are those who really “live” within the moment – saying “yes” to life – as opposed to the slaves who deny themselves. However, that seems to say no to the very concept of exploring and relationships within one’s own existence – a reference back to Kierkegaard, yes, but still a major part of existentialist thought.
I feel as if I simply have the wrong interpretation, but what would seem to help define the truly existential would be the one who lives in both the master and slave mentalities – having the two battling inside of them in an ever changing hierarchy. Caught in that anxious, undefined no-man’s-land a single individual would find it possible to contemplate the extent of his being to an almost limitless end.
Feel free to correct me, if I am in error. Thanks.
Breaking Free of the Rational World
What happened to the original "strong" class?
I find a problem with Nietzsche’s argument in that it seems to take away are perceived sense of free will and decision making. While it is true that some people are naturally stronger than others and some are weaker, it does not mean that they follow in accordance with their nature every time. If we are to be reduced to our base state of our instinct and act naturally according to whatever it is in our nature, then it seems as if we do have free will or any choice in the decision making process. This also destroys the whole sense of morality in our conscience today, which is what Nietzsche aims to do, as everyone perceives themselves as being moral, and having the ability to make conscience decisions about their actions. If Nietzsche’s ideas about the reversal of the classes and nature of the slave and the strong class, does this mean that all the Nietzsche-ian strong no longer exist if everyone believes that they have a moral choice, therefore making everyone part of the slave class? Or is it that even these strong at this point can act as the strong, they are just falsely believing in their choice and their inner strength leads them to act a certain way regardless of their perceived free will?
The Universe in Fecal Terms
Nietzsche is perceptive, too, in linking the otherworldly value system (Judeo-Christian morality) that rejects purely naturalistic values to those individuals who are lacking in precisely those qualities (strength, power, health, etc.) that our status as natural beings forces us to desire. After all, Christianity historically found the greatest purchase among precisely the most down- of ancient society,and the emergence of the Jewish religion is likewise traceable to the history of subjugation of that people.
Clever as it may be, all this is not quite as subversive as it sounds; Christianity, after all, explicitly uses language and concepts such as slavery and self-denial in explaining itself. Nietzsche merely appropriates this language with a sneer. And ultimately, one must ask why the posited "slave revolt" succeeded. I would argue that it derives from the ultimate futility of the naturalistic values of the "aristocratic" morality. Even for the strong, the beautiful, the healthy, existence is ultimately hedged about by factors beyond one's control, and everything ultimately is subject to our mortality. The monotheistic religions, as with other mythological accounts of humanity, attempt to explain the origins of death and imperfection that we see in the physical realm, and furthermore offer means of ultimately countering or even conquering this chaotic reality through spiritual means.
Because of this universal appeal, this is why even those among us who do not accept the theological contentions of revealed religion are usually loath to accept Nietzsche "aristocratic" morality, or interpret the whole of Western tradition with such contempt. We are creatures of natural drives, but we know instinctively that we are not only so. We are uniquely reflective animals capable of thinking about a good life in terms not only of our immediate desires, or even of the good of the collective, but in terms of a kind of dignity that the lambs and birds of prey do not know. In crude terms, we are the one species that decides what to do with our shit.